RUDN Journal of Philosophy

Editor-in-Chief: Vladimir N. Belov, D.Sc. in Philosophy, Professor

ISSN: 2313-2302 (Print) ISSN: 2408-8900 (Online)

Founded in 1997. Publication frequency: quarterly.

Open Access: Open Access. APC: no article processing charge.

Peer-Review: double blind. Publication language: Russian, English

Journal History

PUBLISHER: Peoples’ Friendship University of Russia named after Patrice Lumumba (RUDN University)

Indexation: Scopus, Russian Index of Science Citation, Google Scholar, Ulrich's Periodicals Directory, WorldCat, East View, Dimensions, DOAJ, ResearchBib, Lens, Research4Life, JournalTOCs, British Library, Bodleian Libraries (University of Oxford), Ghent University Library

 

"RUDN Journal of Philosophy” a peer-reviewed academic journal. For many years, the journal has been a space to feature the best research of the leading Russian and international scholars in the fields of History of Philosophy, Ontology, Theory of Knowledge, Social Philosophy and other areas. Our editorial policy also involves a strong support of young talented scientists throughout the world. The unique experience and traditions of the school of philosophical thought of RUDN University are embodied in philosophical comparativism, which is the top-priority research area of the journal.

Announcements

 

Call for papers: Special issues in 2026

Posted: 18.11.2024

Special theme of the 1st issue 2026: “The Philosophy of Paul Natorp

Call for papers: Special issues in 2025

Posted: 18.11.2024

Special theme of the 1st issue 2025: “The Philosophy of Paul Natorp
Special theme of the 2nd issue 2025: “Contemporary society and social security
Special theme of the 3rd issue 2025: “Philosophy in Latinamerica
Special theme of the 4th issue 2025: “In Search of a Strategy for Teaching Philosophy: Russian and World Experience

Call for papers: Special issues in 2024

Posted: 18.11.2024

Special issue theme 01/2024: "Mahayana Buddhist Philosophy"
Special issue theme 02/2024: "Kant in Russia"
Special issue theme 03/2024: "Post-Neokantianism"
Special issue theme 04/2024: "Experimental Philosophy"

Call for papers: Special issues in 2026

Posted: 10.09.2024

Special theme of the 1st issue 2026: “The Philosophy of Paul Natorp

Call for papers: Special issues in 2024

Posted: 12.04.2024

Special issue theme 01/2024: "Mahayana Buddhist Philosophy"
Special issue theme 02/2024: "Kant in Russia"
Special issue theme 03/2024: "Post-Neokantianism"
Special issue theme 04/2024: "Experimental Philosophy"

CURRENT RESEARCHES ON NEO-KANTIANISM: NEW ISSUES OF JOURNALS

Posted: 15.02.2024

RUDN Journal of Philosophy was mentioned in a compilation of current studies of neo-Kantianism

 
More Announcements...

Current Issue

Vol 28, No 3 (2024): POST-NEO-KANTIANISM

POST-NEO-KANTIANISM

Post-Neo-Kantianism and the Problem of Revival of Systematic Transcendental Philosophy
Zeidler K.W., Belov V.N., Perepechina A.S.
Abstract

With a view to the question of a possible revival of systematic transcendental philosophy, the article follows the problem developments from outgoing neo-Kantianism to post-neo-Kantianism to the present day. Neo-Kantianism decisively determined this development, since, following the ‘analytical method’ of the prolegomena, it based its principletheoretical claim on the ‘factum of science’ and other facta of culture. Since the fact of science and culture at the beginning of the 20th century has changed. However, this ‘validity objectivism’ rapidly lost credibility. Although he was also criticized within neo-Kantianism (Emil Lask, Paul Natorp), these isolated approaches and calls for a renewal and deepening of the reflection of principles remained ineffective, since one sought salvation rather in the forced orientation to individual sciences or in new Orthodoxies and academic ‘research’. For a continuity of transcendental philosophical questions, but by no means for a revival of the systematic transcendental philosophy, the works of vom Verf. under the title Kritische Dialektik und Transcendentalontologie , post-neo-Kantian approaches of the interwar and post-war period by Richard Hönigswald and Wolfgang Cramer, Bruno Bauch and Hans Wagner, as well as Robert Reininger and Erich Heintel, documented a systematically oriented succession in the works of Werner Flach and Harald Holz to the present day, and - under conditions of philosophy of consciousness - in the works of Dieter Henrich and Karl-Otto Apel, an at least there was a thematic continuation. However, a “revival of systematic transcendental philosophy” would require more radical approaches than have been delivered in the last 100 years: it would simply require a return to the ‘synthetic method' of critique of reason , which “bases nothing as a given, except reason itself”.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):635-652
pages 635-652 views
Post-Neo-Kantian Idealism
Krijnen C.
Abstract

In discussion with Kant, neo-Kantianism, and contemporary transcendental philosophy on the one hand and Hegel’s speculative idealism on the other, Krijnen discusses the philosophical form in which post neo-Kantian idealism has a future. First, he determines the type of Kantian transcendental idealism that constitutes its most advanced form. Here, Krijnen distinguishes intersubjectivity-theoretical forms of transcendental philosophy from phenomenology and neo-Kantianism and focusses on phenomenology and neo-Kantianism. In Krijnen’s analysis, a programmatic foundational deficit of phenomenology appears. In terms of a theory of principles, phenomenology falls behind Kant’s conception of philosophical foundations, whereas neo-Kantianism and the contemporary transcendental philosophers discussed continue the relevant programmatic line of Kant’s reasoning. Krijnen subsequently shows that even in its most advanced form, transcendental idealism suffers from formalism. This is due to the fact that transcendental philosophy misses the methodical moment of the ‘realization of the concept’ in the sense Hegel’s speculative idealism. For this reason, ‘form’ and ‘content’ remain opposed to each other externally. Hegel’s reproach of formalism does not state that Kant’s forms are merely empty shells, neglecting the content-logical character of principles in the sense of transcendental idealism. In contrast, Hegel’s reproach concerns a methodical problem that hinders transcendental idealism to actualize its own ambitions. Finally, Krijnen makes clear in what sense a Hegelian sublation of transcendental idealism into speculative idealism is of the essence for the future of post-neo-Kantian idealism.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):653-669
pages 653-669 views
Epistemological Problems of Quantum Mechanics Following Ernst Cassirer and Richard Hönigswald
Breil R.
Abstract

This article deals with the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and its epistemological discussion by Ernst Cassirer and Richard Hönigswald. The starting point is Cassirer's treatise Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics, published in Stockholm. Both philosophers and several physicists were involved in the subsequent exchange of letters. From a physical point of view, the Copenhagen interpretation was particularly criticised by v. Laue and Einstein. Both demanded a revision of the foundations of quantum mechanics or a critical examination of essential physical concepts. The epistemological implications of the Copenhagen interpretation were rejected, in particular that the interactions between observation, the observed and the observer in quantum physics experiments should lead to a renunciation of the concept of causality or an objectively unambiguous description of natural processes. Cassirer argues here that quantum mechanics fulfils the epistemological requirement of transforming ontological “concepts of things” into epistemological concepts of relations and is therefore compatible with the neo-critical approach he advocates. At the same time, Hönigswald was working on two major treatises on the structure of physics and the concept of causality. Here he undertakes an epistemological foundation of physics as a whole. A transcendental foundation of the concept of experience and its specifications in principles such as contemplation, observation or experiment appears to be called for. Hönigswald therefore essentially rejects the Copenhagen interpretation, as it draws epistemological consequences by physical means and thus inadmissibly reverses the transcendentally necessary relations of justification. These arguments are examined and could be used for a current discussion on the epistemological foundations of quantum mechanics and physics as a whole. A post-Neo-Kantian, transcendental philosophical foundation of scientific knowledge, especially of modern physics, seems possible and necessary.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):670-687
pages 670-687 views
Critique of the One Reason. On the Systemic Unity of the Three ‘Critiques’
Bunte M.
Abstract

There is still disagreement among researchers about the question of the intention, unity and coherence of Kant's philosophy. In view of the distance in time to Kant, this state of affairs is as surprising as it is unsatisfactory. It is therefore all the more pleasing that new movement has come into Kant research, particularly as a result of recent research work, but also through the rediscovery of older contributions, which gives hope that certain fundamental questions of Kantian philosophy can indeed be answered. This also applies to the question of the unity and structure of the three critiques to be discussed in this articles. At the centre of this is the thesis that the three critiques, taken together, answer or attempt to answer the basic concern of a comprehensive critique of pure reason, namely to establish reason as the ultimate and self-founding principle of all experience. In itself, each of the three critiques represents a necessary moment of a more comprehensive movement of justification, which the critique as a whole goes through three times. In each of these passages, it encounters aporias that can no longer be resolved from its respective standpoint, but which lead to a necessary consequential standpoint. The order of the critiques of reason follows the classical doctrine of transcendentalism. Thus, reason in the theoretical forms the principle of systematic unity, in the practical forms the principle of objective validity, i.e. of truth, and in the reflection on the universality of the one reason underlying both forms of reason, the principle of perfection. From there, the Critique of Pure Reason as a whole should return to its beginning, namely to the exposition of its presupposition. The fact that Kant himself did not complete his system should not be a cause for regret, but rather lead to philosophising with Kant rather than about him.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):688-696
pages 688-696 views
Transcendental Philosophy and Post-Neo-Kantianism. On the Continuity of the Problem History of Transcendental Systematics in the 20th Century
Boch M.
Abstract

This article aims to make a contribution to the problematic history of the transcendental philosophical tradition up to the present day. At the centre is the question of the continuity of transcendental philosophical research in the 20th century with regard to the situation before and after the Second World War. The decisive point of reference here  is Neo-Kantianism. Canonical Neo-Kantianism research defines it on the basis of its core phase between 1895 and 1912, which it precedes with an emergence and ends with a dissolution. There is no consensus among researchers when it comes to determining and dating the emergence and end of Neo-Kantianism. However, the majority of researchers agree that the end of Neo-Kantianism was between 1918 and 1945, marking a break in this philosophical tradition. Nevertheless, there is also a research perspective that allows a post-history to follow the core phase of Neo-Kantianism. However, the term Neo-Neo-Kantianism proposed for this is rejected by the majority of research in Neo-Kantianism. Kurt Walter Zeidler and Andrej Noras have taken up research into the post-history of Neo-Kantianism in different ways. On the one hand, Zeidler makes Post-Neo-Kantian systematics the guiding principle of his analysis with a view to continuity within the Neo-Kantian school of realist criticism. Andrej Noras, on the other hand, interprets the ontological interpretation of Kant in the 1920s and its critique of epistemologically orientated classical Neo-Kantianism as Post-Neo-Kantianism, which he follows with Neo-Neo-Kantianism as a critique of the critique of Post-Neo-Kantianism. The two authors thus argue in favour of a continuity of the transcendental philosophical tradition in the 20th century, whereby they make the supposed end of neo-Kantianism the starting point of their investigations. In this article, the terms Neo-Kantianism, Neo-Neo-Kantianism and  Post-Neo-Kantianism will be clarified and contextualised within Neo-Kantian research.  On the basis of this presentation, a perspective for the transcendental philosophical systematics of the 21st century will then be developed, which productively appropriates the 20th century  as its problem-historical foundation.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):697-716
pages 697-716 views
Wolfgang Marx as a post-Neo-Kantian: The Reflection of the Reflection of the Reflection
Edel G.
Abstract

This article presents Wolfgang Marx as a post-Neo-Kantian par excellence. Wolfgang Marx begins with an essay on Paul Natorp, then writes a book on Hegel and one on Hermann Cohen and from there his first major work, “Reflexionstopologie” (1984). In this book, Wolfgang Marx denies that the great epistemological goals of traditional philosophy, such as, in a Hegelian perspective, finding an ‘intrinsically’ first thought from which all further thoughts could be gained, or also an ‘intrinsically’ final thought in and with which philosophical thought would come to a definitive end, are achievable at all. Accordingly, there is no “unity of the world after the unity of the Logos”. These philosophical-critical theses explain why Wolfgang Marx’s philosophy is hardly recognised by the established philosophical establishment. After “Reflexionstopologie”, the second main work, “Bewusstseins-Welten” (1994), is also presented. This book now relates the insights gained with regard to pure thinking in the “topology of reflection” to consciousness and concretises them therein. Finally, it is presented that Wolfgang Marx has expressed himself in a wealth of individual publications on various topics. These include personalised questions about Rudolf Carnap and Martin Heidegger, but also purely systematic questions such as the relevance of the philosophical concept of the system.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):717-725
pages 717-725 views

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

Logical and Epistemological Doctrine of Leonid E. Gabrilovich on Mathematical Thinking and Actual Form
Shevtsov A.V.
Abstract

The research examines the logical and epistemological studies of Leonid Evgenievich Gabrilovich (1878-1953), a Russian philosopher, logic and engineer, and subsequently a Russian-American thinker. The works of L.E. Gabrilovich still remain practically unknown or little known in Russian philosophy. In the study of the philosophical concept of one of the main works of L.E. Gabrilovich “On Mathematical Thinking and the Concept of the Actual Form” (1914), the study of the theory of “actual forms”, which clarifies the foundations of human thinking, is central to the attention of readers. It is proved that the topics of mathematical formalism, the system of experience, the actual form and the problems of number touched upon by Gabrilovich were logical and epistemological aspects of his philosophy. The research covers the content of a review of this essay by Gabrilovich of the famous German mathematician and logic Leopold Löwenheim, published in 1915. The similarity of the theory of actual forms Gabrilovich’s and the meaning of the Löwenheim theorem is revealed. The analysis of Gabrilovich’s work conducted here covers little-known pages of Russian philosophical thought and should serve to enrich and fill existing lacunae in the study of Russian philosophy of the 20th century. In the process of studying the central work of Gabrilovich, results were obtained, on the basis of which they came to the conclusion that the Russian thinker sought to build a complete system of the science of philosophy. In his emigration, Gabrilovich turned to the legacy of such Russian philosophers as Vladimir Solovyov and Nikolai Berdyaev, which was surprisingly combined with mathematical thinking and the concept of actual forms. The study outlines the prospects for studying this and other works of Gabrilovich in the context of neo-Kantianism and the philosophy of mathematics. The original theory of “actual forms” proposed by Gabrilovich can be considered the result of a philosophical understanding of the foundations of mathematics, which was characteristic precisely for logical and epistemological philosophical searches.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):726-739
pages 726-739 views
The Refraction of Byzantine and Ancient Russian Ideas in the Ethical and Political Writings of John IV the Terrible
Volkova A.A.
Abstract

The research is devoted to the study of the ethical origins and foundations of patriotism in the letters of the first Russian tsar John the Terrible to Prince Andrei Kurbsky. The epistolary legacy of the Russian sovereign, directed primarily to domestic and foreign policy opponents, reveals a synthesis of ethical and ideological-political overtones. John's argumentation system is based on the focus of consideration of the problem of evil and responsibility for it and is based on the Eastern Christian tradition, according to which the concepts of evil and sin are identical, and the most terrible sin is betrayal of God. It is shown that in addition to Byzantine sources, the paradigm of the ethical and political constructions of John the Terrible also includes Russian ones (“Teaching” of Vladimir Monomakh, “Enlightener” and the Epistles of Joseph Volotsky, “The Tale of the Princes of Vladimir”), which allows us to conclude that the concept of evil of the Russian Tsar acquires a patriotic sound due to inclusion of new components in the Byzantine scheme of ideas about true evil. According to John the Terrible, the most terrible sin is treason to God, the Motherland and the tsar. The study analyzes John the Terrible's philosophical understanding of the concepts of Homeland and sovereign, acting as microcosmic and macrocosmic models, often identified with each other. The concept of the Motherland in John IV's worldview is a combination of such images as the macrocosm (a living organism), the state (empire), the Orthodox island (“third Rome” and “Holy Russia”). The sovereign of all Russia, according to the medieval thinker, combines the signs of a human and a superpersonal (the vicar of God, responsible for all his people). The mission of the Russian tsar as one of the main forms of service and protection of the Motherland is seen by John in the fight against true evil.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):740-756
pages 740-756 views

ONTOLOGY AND GNOSEOLOGY

The Beginnings of Metaphilosophy: Heinrich Struve vs. Morris Laserowitz
Skripnik K.D.
Abstract

The recognition of metaphilosophy as a separate independent philosophical discipline forces us to pay attention not only to the various variants of its understanding and its own status, but also to the history of its origin and development. It is believed that the beginning of metaphilosophy as a study of the nature of philosophy was laid by several articles by M. Lazerowitz, although some other philosophers are mentioned in passing. The study characterizes Lazerowitz’s desire to understand metaphilosophy as a view of philosophy “from the outside” and demonstrates the failure of this attempt: in fact, his metaphilosophy represents a position “inside” philosophy itself. The author of the research argues that the beginning of philosophy of philosophy should be associated with the works of the Russian and Polish philosopher Heinrich Struve and suggests a broader reconstruction of his approach. A comparison of the works of these philosophers makes it possible to identify their common starting point, which is the statement of the presence of many disagreements in philosophy, that is, what Kant called a “scandal” in philosophy. The differences between the two approaches are also revealed, in particular, Struve’s philosophy of philosophy is a precursor to any philosophy in general, aimed, while maintaining the different points of view of individual philosophers, at developing a “common worldview”. As the subject of his philosophy of philosophy, Struve calls a historical and critical analysis of the current state of philosophy, an explanation of the subject, tasks, goals, aspirations and method of philosophy; among the “principles” of philosophy is the study of the relationship of philosophy to other “phenomena of mental life.” In addition to Lazerowitz and Struve, the author points to other philosophers (for example, J. Maritain, V. Ern, E. Kalinowsky, T. Oizerman), whose interests include metaphilosophical problems, and a detailed study of their works can help to see a certain historical tradition of metaphilosophy.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):757-770
pages 757-770 views
Militarization of Artificial Intelligence Systems: Opportunities and Threats
Gnatik E.N.
Abstract

The research is devoted to considering the possibilities and risks of using artificial intelligence in military affairs. It is emphasized that at present, when the importance of the factor of military force has significantly increased in the world, artificial intelligence technologies are increasingly being considered as one of the basic tools for strengthening the potential of militarization. Along with other breakthrough innovations, such systems are a priority in the creation of promising weapons, military and special equipment. The conditions of growing tension in the modern confrontation are stimulating an unprecedented increase in the pace of scientific and technical development of “smart” weapons, their serial industrial production, testing and use on the battlefield. The development of artificial intelligence technologies is actively bringing forward a fundamental transformation of the scientific and technical equipment of the defense sector and leading to the emergence of new trends in the development of military art. Analyzing the phenomenon of opacity of artificial intelligence, the author notes the tendency of these systems to turn into a kind of black boxes, which significantly complicates the understanding of the principles, algorithms, sequence of actions on the basis of which the system makes conclusions, decisions, etc. This entails the impossibility of properly monitoring the adequacy of the data obtained using these systems, and even more so of “automatically” trusting them. These circumstances increase potential risks, since the use of weapons equipped with artificial intelligence platforms significantly reduces the operator’s ability to control the situation in the combat area, minimizing the time to comprehend the situation and make a strategic decision. The author believes that the main threat of the transition from robotization to the intellectualization of weapons and military equipment is the removal of humans from decision-making. Going beyond clearly understood and defined algorithms is a danger that cannot be ignored. The cost of an error made as a result of an inadequate decision made by a digital service may turn out to be unacceptably high. The study notes that weapons equipped with artificial intelligence are more dangerous than traditional means of warfare due to speed and elements of unpredictability. Such developments can become a powerful catalyst for the onset of the era of the next technological structure, where the main guideline is the creation of systems of strong (general) artificial intelligence.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):771-784
pages 771-784 views
On Supervenience
Petrov V.B.
Abstract

A logical formalization of the supervenience relation is proposed, allowing it to be presented as a logical, theoretical or factual relation between an individual property and another property, between an individual property and a set of properties, between two sets of properties. The main logical properties of these relations are characterized, an assessment of the known definitions of weak individual supervenience, strong individual supervenience and global supervenience associated with the concept of possible worlds is given from the standpoint of the proposed formalization. The difference between the understanding of the term "property" in classical predicate logic and the understanding of this term beyond it is emphasized. Possible interpretations of D. Davidson's thesis on the supervenience of mental characteristics on physical characteristics are considered. It is demonstrated that Davidson’s thesis does not correspond to any of the supervenience relations, the formalization of which was presented. An example of a scheme of an ideal hypothetically possible experiment is given, the results of which could refute the thesis on the supervenience of mental characteristics on physical ones. Arguments are put forward in favor of a skeptical position regarding the possibility of solving the problem of supervenience of the mental on the physical. Two types of possible situations are described in which supervenience of some properties on other properties can be discovered. It is shown that in situations of each of these types the supervenience relation is discovered as a consequence of some stronger type of connection, thereby revealing its secondary nature relative to the correlation dependencies between the properties (sets of properties) of the objects under study that are actually recorded in experience or theoretically substantiated. It is concluded that the significance of the idea of supervenience in analytical philosophy is overestimated.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):785-795
pages 785-795 views
Art and Science as a Subject of Aesthetic Epistemology
Kolomiets G.G.
Abstract

The author defines the subject of aesthetic epistemology in the increasingly complex process of a unified meta-system of art, science and technology. Using the concept of “aesthetic epistemology”, the author follows the original premise of aesthetics as a philosophical science in the field of epistemology, discovered by A.G. Baumgarten - the science of sensory cognition, the ability to think beautifully in images, and then enriched by the aesthetic idea of I. Kant, the transcendental ability of aesthetic judgment, requiring entry into creative activity in art and science. The author notes the ambivalence in the views of modern philosophers and physicists on the relationship between art and science, rational and non-logical, logic and intuition, referring to the authority of scientist E.L. Feinberg. At the same time, the idea is emphasized that aesthetic epistemology contributes to the unity of the anthroposocioecological complex meta-system. Attention is drawn to the aesthetic ideal of harmony present in art, science, and technology. Thus, for the musical creativity of modern times, the mathematical complication of sound ratios with the help of modern computer technologies is characteristic, similar to the complication of the dynamics of the development of the whole meta-system of science and art, in which it is important to emphasize the action of the intuitive principle in the aesthetic consciousness of a person. For aesthetic epistemology, the problem of science growing into art is relevant. In modern aesthetics, there is a tendency to reduce the “beautiful” and increase interest in the unusual in art due to new technologies, revealing the secrets of the aesthetic unconscious. Summarizing, the author asserts the idea that aesthetic epistemology determines the forms of modern art and scientific knowledge as a single meta-system and that humanity needs the unity of art, science and technology for the purpose of its existence. This is facilitated by intuition and a deep aesthetic property with the ability of imagination and symbolic thinking. Art and science are rapidly evolving in an increasingly complex integration process aimed at the conscious desire of a person to realize creative ideas based on supersensible, sensual, aesthetic cognition.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):796-810
pages 796-810 views
The Struggle with Correlationism: Speculative Realism against Heidegger
Devaykin I.A.
Abstract

The main problem that speculative realism, represented by Quentin Meillassoux, Graham Harman and Ray Brassier, is trying to solve is overcoming correlationism. Two important figures who played a key role in the development of correlationism are Immanuel Kant and Martin Heidegger. Correlationism is a type of philosophizing that postulates that a person has access only to the connection (correlation) between the subject and the thing in itself, but not to these instances separately. The correlation is often anthropic in nature, i.e. it is language, social practices, culture, consciousness, history, meaning, and so on. Speculative realism seeks to overcome correlationism and show how one can approach the thing in itself. Heidegger played a significant role in the development of correlationism - speculative realists are in active dialogue with him. It is shown that the interpretation and criticism of Heidegger's ideas by speculative realists is untenable. Speculative realists are often even greater correlationists than Heidegger, since they replace the concept of the thing in itself with the thing for us. It is concluded that correlationism cannot be overcome, but it is necessary to reduce its influence through a number of techniques. Such practices include the restoration of the idea of the Kantian thing in itself. It is also necessary to introduce the idea of a passive subject who reduces his cognitive claims and switches attention to the affect of the thing in itself. In addition, we must remember that the human race is not the center of the world drama, and its fate depends on how carefully it learns to handle natural forces that exist independently of it in order to avoid climate catastrophe.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):811-820
pages 811-820 views

HISTORY OF EASTERN PHILOSOPHY

The Cosmological Archetype of War in Sun-zi Treatise “Bing fa”
Abramenko V.P.
Abstract

The proposed research analyzes for the first time the text of the ancient Chinese treatise “The Art of War” (兵法 bing fa ) from the point of view of the presence in it of archetypal constructions designed to tame chaos in such a phenomenon of human society as war. This written work of the Chinese strategist and thinker Sun-zi has been thoroughly analyzed into phrases and words by specialists of various disciplines, but all in one key - in the key of war. In this paper, other research goals of this treatise are formulated, consisting in tracking the process of embedding elements of military affairs into the cosmological archetype of Tao. It is particularly noted that, in essence, by creating the “Bing Fa”, Sun-zi accomplished what no theorist of the art of war could do. He presented the cosmological archetype of war in the form of a sequential set of five archetypal elements, relying in its construction on the Taoist model of the cosmological archetype of Tao. In the world triad of Heaven - Man - Earth, the central place of Sun-zi is occupied by a military subject: a Warlord - Commander-in-Chief, a Warrior. From now on, a commander who knows the military craft must be responsible for the fate of his people, ensure the security of the state, its power and invulnerability. It can be traced that, in essence, civilization acts as a breeding ground for warriors and war, and Taoism together with Confucianism can be incorporated into the civilizational space only with their support of the prevailing state ideology.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):821-832
pages 821-832 views
On the European Roots of the Identity Crisis in Japanese Aesthetics of the ХХ-ХХI centuries
Skvortsova E.L.
Abstract

During the second half of the 20th century aesthetical students in Japan demonstrated growing activity, aimed at the investigation in the field of national aesthetical heritage applying the method of hermeneutics. The Western forms of philosophical thought and comparative studies were supposed to be necessary for this purpose. But there appeared a group of young scientists, who chose the road of national alienation, who stressed the specific features of Japanese culture in general and the essence of art in particular - Sakabe Megumi, Sasaki Ken’ichi, Iwaki Ken’ichi. As a result, two quite bright but different trends in Japanese aesthetics emerged. They disagree on a number of issues related to the status of aesthetics as a philosophical science and art as a professional activity. At the same time representatives of both movements consider themselves heirs to the ideas of the famous philosopher Nishida Kitaro. Thus, Amagasaki Akira, who shared the point of view of this group on the altering the status of art in the epoch of predominating of mass culture, proposed to give up the previous concept of art, implying professionalism, high quality of works, systematic study and, so to say, sacred horizon, that is the strive for abandoning the frames of mundane world, which are the characteristic features of Western image of art. The aesthetics of ХХ-ХХI centuries in Japan demonstrated variety of opinions: on the one hand, it was the strive for theoretical reconstruction of the fundamental elements of the traditional artistic thought, drawing towards philosophical analysis applying the methods of Western thought. On the other - we see the return movement back to traditional heritage giving up Western methodology and insisting on immediate, spontaneous individual experience abandoning any generalization, which is a kind of “aesthetical nominalism”.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):833-847
pages 833-847 views
The Bhagavad Gita through the Prism of Kantian Ethics
Kortunov V.V., Lapshin I.Y., Panyukov A.I.
Abstract

The study analyzes one of the main works of Hindu philosophy, the Bhagavad Gita, which tremendously influenced the development of the Eastern image of the world in general and the Hindu in particular. The concept of paths leading to liberation and cognition of “Self”, God, being and non-being is considered. The authors conclude that the path of knowledge (Djnâna Marga), although it should contain both intellectual principles and rational tools, contains the subordination of intellect to intuition, which contradicts the European philosophical thought. Another path of liberation is the path of action (service) - Karma Marga, the most difficult task of which is to overcome the interest in performing an action. Service should be free from selfish considerations. Here Kant expressed views very close to Karma Marga, focusing on the philosophical analysis of the moral and legal. As proof, the authors analyze examples of human actions that cannot be evaluated unambiguously. The third path of the Gita is the path of love (devotion), gaining unity with God. There is no clear commentary in the work on which of the paths is most important, but the path of love itself is a result that the other two paths only strive for. The authors conclude that there is a difference between Western and Eastern culture. In Eastern philosophy, the truth is revealed not on the path to rational knowledge, but on the path of the aesthetics of love. However, the authors note that Western religion includes the concept of love, but it has a fundamentally different character. In Western Christianity, a person places God in their heart, and in Indian systems, a person must find a way to the heart of God.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):848-857
pages 848-857 views

SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY

Utopian Consciousness: an Anthropological Universal and a Socio-Cultural Construct
Zolotukhina-Abolina E.V.
Abstract

The research is devoted to the status and role of utopian consciousness in society and culture. The author believes that the utopian component is inherent in any human goal-setting and design. A project is the result of dissatisfaction with the current reality; it carries within itself a desire for change, radical restructuring, but at first a person is dominated by desire and an as yet unformed image - both the goal and the path to its implementation. Therefore, the first phase of design is always utopian. In sociocultural design, this is the “image of paradise”, which only later develops into realistic plans and selection of funds, taking into account circumstances. However, the utopian component as an ideal remains an inspiring moment with a clear distinction between ideal and reality. Utopian consciousness acquires the features of an illusion when the ideal is transferred to specific actual space and time. Then people try to either “move” to Eden, or transport it to themselves, or quickly realize it, in a hurry and getting tired. In the first case, one’s own “project for the best” is abandoned; in the second, one tries to implement one’s own project without taking into account real possibilities. In both cases, disappointment follows due to the lack of realism. The study also analyzes utopian consciousness as a social construct created by influential social groups to realize their interests. This construct is spread through the media. The author believes that ideologies, including those produced by existing power, are always at the same time utopias for the masses. Two powerful modern utopias are briefly examined - globalist-technocratic and conservative-archaic, noting their unrealistic nature, leading to subsequent disappointments.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):858-871
pages 858-871 views
The Ethics of Conflict in Changing World
Chernyak A.Z., Ivleva M.L.
Abstract

In the study, conflict is understood mainly as the actions aimed at harming the opposing side, since only in this sense is war considered as an object of moral assessments and recommendations. The authors address the problem of the transformation of the role of the Theory of Just War (JWT), which is currently the dominant ethics of war and defines the essence of the difference between fair and unfair war. The study highlights the problems of using JWT, analyzes more detailly the problem of reconciling JWT with the changing realities of war. The authors consider and criticize N. Fotion’s solution, according to which two different modifications of JWT instead of one are used - JWT for regular and irregular wars. The most obvious alternative solutions were analyzed and the authors conclude that the least problematic solution is to reject the identification of morally justified wars with the fair ones and to assume the existence of morally justified wars that are not fair. This allows to interpret actions that do not meet moral requirements, but have some moral justification in special situations, as exceptions, not because in these cases they cease to be morally wrong or fair, but because the circumstances that make them morally justified are such that strict observance of the general rule creates too high a risk of even worse moral consequences. By this assumption another contradiction is resolved: aggression may remain a form of injustice, but in some cases it may have a moral justification. The solution proposed by the authors only sets a promising direction for solving the problem. At the same time, it is still important to minimize the risk of situations in which it will be necessary to choose between justice and the moral justification of war.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):872-884
pages 872-884 views
Confucian Thesis of Moral Politics and its Development
Tsai W., Chistyakov D.I., Chistyakova O.V.
Abstract

This paper aims to examine Confucian thesis of moral politics. By comparing three types of administration, Confucius’ thoughts on the problematics of moral politics are analyzed in more detail, highlighting the inner tension between the moral and the political. The difficulty of the concept is shown by discussing its development so that the validity question can be brought to the fore. In order to conduct a comprehensive analysis of the moral politics, it is necessary to first address three distinct approaches to its development. We call the consanguinity-based system of administration of the Western Zhou feudal system Lĭ-Chìh (禮治). This implies using the rites (禮) as the primary means of state governance. Comparatively speaking, the morality-governed administrative method is known as Dé-Chìh (德治). The third, Fă-Chìh (法治), denotes that laws are the basis for state governance. The interdependence of rites, morals, and law makes it impossible to simply divide the three modes of administration. The theory of moral politics offers new avenues for development since China adopted the democratic system. A group of Chinese academics known as the New Confucians attempted to integrate this theory with the democratic system in the early 20th century in an attempt to find a fresh approach to the theory’s application issue. This theory still revolves around Dé-Chìh. Fă-Chìh’s authenticity is amply verified. The New Confucians regard the conflict between Dé-Chíh and Dé-Chìh as a dialectical evolution.

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):885-902
pages 885-902 views

SCHOLARLY LIFE

Cultural Philosophy: from Monotheism to Monism
Frolova E.A.
Abstract

-

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):903-907
pages 903-907 views
Immanuel Kant’s Philosophy through the Prism of Time: on the 300th Anniversary of the Philosopher’s Birth
Rybakov O.Y.
Abstract

-

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):908-915
pages 908-915 views
An Interpretation of the Topical Social-Ontological Problems within the Russian Ontological Tradition: Review of the Monograph “Contemporary Social Ontology in the Mirror of the Russian Ontological Tradition: Discourses and Interpretations” by Orekhov A.M., Platonova S.V., Maracha V.G. et. al.
Latypov I.A.
Abstract

-

RUDN Journal of Philosophy. 2024;28(3):916-921
pages 916-921 views

This website uses cookies

You consent to our cookies if you continue to use our website.

About Cookies