Vol 29, No 1 (2025): THE PHILOSOPHY OF PAUL NATORP
- Year: 2025
- Articles: 18
- URL: https://journals.rudn.ru/philosophy/issue/view/1841
- DOI: https://doi.org/10.22363/2313-2302-2025-29-1
Full Issue
THE PHILOSOPHY OF PAUL NATORP
Paul Natorp as Musician, Composer and Music Theorist: А Historical-Biographical Sketch
Abstract
The musician and composer Paul Natorp has not been recognised in research. The references in his Self-Presentation (Selbstdarstellung) (1921) to the importance of music, especially in his early years, have so far remained unacknowledged. The musical legacy and previously unpublished diaries and letters provide more detailed information. They demonstrate the young Natorp’s passionate relationship with music. In addition, it becomes clear that Natorp was active as a composer throughout his life. The article starts by describing the musical legacy. At the centre is the correspondence with Johannes Brahms, to whom the young Natorp submitted some of his compositions for review. Brahms strongly advised against a career as a musician and composer. Also significant are reports from the young Natorp about his composition studies with the musicologist and composer Gustav Jacobsthal (1845-1912) in Strasbourg. Reports on concerts with Clara Schumann and Franz Liszt are biographical and cultural-historical documents. The article concludes with a sketch of Natorp's reflections on the world-historical significance of Ludwig van Beethoven’s music.


Natorp and Cohen on the Problem of Religion in Modernity
Abstract
In this study Paul Natorpʼs writing Religion within the Limits of Humanity is interpreted as a treatment of the problem of religion in modernity, which takes up and transforms the impulses of Kant and Schleiermacher. Five aspects of this problem, which were already present in Schleiermacher’s Speeches on religion , are once again a subject of further processing in the medium of the Neo-Kantian discourse in Marburg encluding encounters with Hermann Cohen and Wilhelm Herrmann. One of the answers found here points ahead to Hans Blumenbergʼs St. Matthew Passion . The latterʼs late work at the end of the 20th century can be read within the horizon of these earlier discourses at its beginning as a variation of a musico-dramatic treatment of existential and religious fundamental questions in a general culture affected to change.


Paul Natorp on Plato’s Ideas
Abstract
The research is focused on the analysis of Paul Natorp’s work Plato’s Doctrine of Ideas . The paper consists of three sections: 1) a definition of Platonic idea; 2) an analysis of the dialogue Parmenides ; and 3) a commentary on Natorp’s interpretation of Parmenides . The first section discusses Natorp’s transcendental method, which he uses as a critical approach to philosophical problems. The application of this method to the history of philosophy is examined, and it is shown that, thanks to Natorp, transcendentalism finds its history beginning with Plato and leading through Descartes and Kant to Cohen and the Marburg School of Neo-Kantianism. According to this method, the core of Plato’s doctrine is idealism. Natorp’s definition of the Platonic idea is examined. Parmenides dialogue, in which Plato attempts to formulate his concept of the idea. The analysis focuses on the problem of the scope of ideas, the interaction between ideas and things, and the relationship between empirical and pure ideas. It traces some of Natorp’s steps in defending his thesis that ideas are methods of apprehending the object of knowledge. The third section questions the adequacy of Natorp’s proposed epistemological treatment of Plato’s concept of idea. A counterargument to each of Natorp’s main arguments is presented in turn. Finally, with reference to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason , an alternative interpretation of the discussion between Socrates and Parmenides in the dialogue is given. Its essence, in contrast to Natorp’s affirmative interpretation, which presents Parmenides’ deductions as a development of Plato’s theory, is summed up in the fact that this dialogue represents Plato’s criticism of Parmenides’ approach of taking the ultimate pure concepts as essences and then, on this basis, developing his doctrine of being based, as it were, on the internal logic of these essences themselves. The paper concludes with a discussion of Natorp’s historical-philosophical method, which predetermined his interpretation of Plato’s concept of idea.


On the Systematic Role of the Deduction of Categories in “The Logical Foundations of the Exact Sciences”
Abstract
This work studies the systematic role of the deduction of categories in Paul Natorp’s Logical Foundations of the Exact Sciences. Through an analysis of the deduction of the categories of quantity and quality, we contend that this deduction is not merely a historiographical exercise, but it is the core of Natorp’s system. It is argued that Natorp follows a synthetic method, rather than an analytic, similar to that employed by Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason . We argue that the core of Natorp’s deduction is rooted in the principle of correlation. Unlike Kant, who derives categories from the table of judgments, Natorp constructs his deduction by examining the structure of thought itself. We demonstrate that this approach allows for a systematic deduction of the properties of number and the fundamental series. The study shows how this deduction of categories is the ground for the construction of the fundamental series and how it is aligned with Natorp’s methodological prescriptions.


The Transcendental Method of Paul Natorp
Abstract
In the historical-philosophical literature devoted to the neo-Kantianism of the Marburg School, not enough space is given to the thematisation of Paul Natorp’s transcendental method. Besides, it is of natural scientific interest to explicate the differences in the methods of Kant and the philosophers of the Marburg School. It is supposed that such differences are caused by the ‘incommensurability’ of the paradigms of science on which the philosophers orientated themselves. The aims of the article are (1) to explicate Natorp’s doctrine of the transcendental method; (2) to analyse the differences in Natorp’s and Cohen’s views on this transcendental strategy; (3) to demonstrate the divergence of Kant’s and the Marburgians’ views on method. For Kant, the critical method is a fundamental strategy of analysing the conditions of the possibility of a priori cognition, its essence and origin, scope and limits, principles and laws of application, tools and mechanisms. With Cohen, the transcendental method is not only a strategy of researching scientific experience, but also a genetic, generating tool of scientific thinking. Cohen’s method is oriented towards judgements rather than categories, as was the case with Kant. Natorp’s transcendental method is (1) a meta-method of research and justification of systematic scientific knowledge and (2) a genetic way of generating knowledge and then building a scientific system. The method is initially oriented to the ‘fact of science’ and provides justification of the conditions of possibility of scientific knowledge as a whole. The properties of the method include its critical, immanent, reflexive, and self-generating character. Natorp’s transcendental method works within the logic of pure cognition, but also in ethics, aesthetics, philosophy of religion, and philosophy of consciousness. In doing so, it is oriented towards the genetic basic logical forms (and further, the generating categories) as the a priori tool for the production of science. This focus of Natorp’s method distinguishes it from Cohen’s logic, which focuses on judgements (the foundations of experience), and from Kant’s criticism, which concentrates on synthetic a priori categories.


Paul Natorp’s General Psychology and Its Limits
Abstract
According to Natorp, “consciousness” is characterised by the immediate knowledge of having ideas that can become knowledge. “Consciousness” is the epitome of this knowledge. Natorp confronts it with the idea of a possible consciousness at all as the general expression of appearance. It represents the lawfulness of appearance, the determination of which demands of every empirical consciousness that determines itself to think cognition the differentiation of its “self” from the continuous flow of its states. Accordingly, “consciousness” means the crisis as the zero point of all determination, which of course does not itself determine anything, but rather places “determination in general” in the relationship of the ideas of a consciousness to thinking as the predicate of “consciousness in general”, which must be able to accompany all its ideas - thus also those by virtue of which it perceives itself as thinking. The zero point of determination is therefore the synthetic unity of that which is possible to think and that which is necessary for its representation. For Natorp, the problem of a general psychology therefore consists in how the “I think” as the act of determining my existence can be made generally representable and comprehensible. The fundamental significance of her question, however, is represented by ethics, whose fundamental significance, according to Natorp, is the ultimate task of philosophy.



Critique and System: Early and Late Natorp’s Philosophy
Abstract
This paper presents an interpretation of the connection between Natorp’s early and late philosophy. An analysis of two versions of Natorp’s deduction of categories shows the consistent development of Natorp’s thought. Each deduction expresses, in Natorp’s words, a direction of movement between the centre and the periphery. The early deduction moves from the periphery to the centre by means of the transcendental method. The critical investigation of the conditions of possibility of mathematical-physical science reveals the structure of thought itself. The late deduction is oriented in the opposite direction, from the centre to the periphery. Thought now develops freely and establishes the systematic character of philosophy. We argue that the two deductions complement each other in a single coherent position that accounts for the relationship between critique and system. Philosophical systematics is conceived as the necessary sequel and culmination of an inquiry, the first part of which is developed according to the transcendental method.



Paul Natorp’s Social Pedagogy in Sergei Hessen’s Axiological Historism
Abstract
Sergei (Sergey, Sergius) Hessen, inspired by the ideas of Heinrich Rickert, proposed an axiological interpretation of history as a process of realization of values in the form of material culture. Hessen shows human freedom in the axiological interpretation of Kantian ethics of duty as participation in the realization of values in historical reality. The whole variety of the content of realized values constitutes culture, which is the product not of an individual, but of society as a whole. Hessen’s axiological historism needed to substantiate the individual’s free will as a condition for the possibility of the sociocultural process. Under the influence of Paul Natorp’s social pedagogy, Hessen identified the correlation between individual freedom and societal goals of development. In social pedagogy, Natorp reasoned that society creates and develops culture when the correlation of individual freedom and social development goals is ensured. An understanding of the mutual dependence of the individual and society is provided by the school. The creation and deepening of the content of material culture depends on the creativity of many free people. This study will reveal how Hessen adopts and interprets the ideas of Natorp’s social pedagogy to substantiate the principles of interaction between the individual and society in the process of realization of values - formation of cultural content. It is established that Hessen, following Natorp, interprets education broadly as a process of socialization, and pedagogy as its instrument. Education offers a way to relate the individual and society, teaches that they are interrelated and interdependent in sociocultural development. Hessen overcomes the limitation of approaches to understanding society, focused on the priority of the individual/society, by emphasizing their interaction. Hessen uses this idea of organizing society as a collective social subject consisting of free people not only in pedagogy, but also in socio-political philosophy, forming the doctrine of social law. Hessen views the treatment of society in Natorp’s socio-political works as a development of his ideas of social pedagogy in socio-political philosophy. On this evidence, we can conclude that in his pedagogy, Natorp formed a concept of society that extends beyond pedagogy to his social philosophy as a whole.



Natorp, Husserl and Pure Logic
Abstract
The systematic confrontation between neo-Kantianism and phenomenology was strongly influenced by the dialogue between Natorp and Husserl, which largely dealt with the question of the relationship between subjectivity and objectivity, between the “bottom up” description promoted by the phenomenological method and the “top down” construction that characterizes instead the transcendental method. At the root of this passionate philosophical dispute, however, there is also another issue that is not always adequately considered: the nature of pure logic in the context of the rejection of psychologism. My paper focuses on this aspect and, in particular, examines Natorp’s anti-psychologistic conception of knowledge and his extensive discussion of Husserl’s Prolegomena to Pure Logic .



Lecture on Paul Natorp and Hermann Cohen in Marburg 1948
Abstract
Nicolai Hartmann delivered the lecture on Hermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, published here for the first time, in 1948 in Marburg. He had studied under both scholars since 1905 and had begun his academic career there. However, in his later works Hartmann distanced himself from the thought of his former mentors. Therefore, this late lecture seems all the more striking. In his speech, he draws an impressive portrait of the two personalities, especially of Natorp. Alongside conceptual sketches of their thinking, he shares insights into their personal style in the lectures and seminars they taught.



HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
The First Experiments in Russia to Obtain a Degree in Philosophy
Abstract
The paper attempts to identify the period in Russia when professional specialization in scientific and educational spheres is formed. To solve this problem, the author takes into account the institutional segment of philosophy in Russia, first of all, the university. Then he identifies the functionality of holders of academic degrees “Master of Philosophy”, determines the moment when and how, where and under what conditions philosophy becomes a designation of professional interests. To achieve this goal, the author analyzes the activities of the teaching corporation of metropolitan (Moscow, St. Petersburg) and provincial (Kazan, Kiev) universities of the Russian Empire. The author pays attention to the content of the actual educational process and research activities, and also takes into account the normative documents of general and private character ((local, regional levels, governmental orders, University Statutes). To form the context, the author pays attention to the interaction of academic corporations with state structures (Ministry of Public Education, Senate, Synod), takes into account the mindset of society, ideological background, and political situation. All this makes it possible to record important moments when philosophy, from a kind of “private case” of professional training, from a “secondary element” of professional development, is gradually transformed into a life choice, into a professional activity, into one of the dominant spheres of the academic community.



The Image of the Future through the Prism of the Scientific Views of J.A. Condorcet
Abstract
The research examines the views of J. A. Condorcet, one of the most prominent representatives of the galaxy of European enlighteners. The detailed development and substantiation by the French thinker of the idea of social progress, the main driving force of which is the human mind, still arouses research interest today, more than 230 years later. The current radical change in philosophical views on human improvement and human nature in general is associated with the spread of transhumanist ideas. Attempts to establish a new world order are accompanied by the development of an image of the “desired future” in the form of a social model of the transhumanist concept. Its popularization and the desire to move from the host of philosophical ideas to the practical sphere are facilitated, first of all, by reliance on a modern scientific and technological foundation, the increased capabilities of nano-, bio-, info- and cognitive sciences. The authors of the research focus on the question: are today’s ideas about human improvement a reconstruction of intentions based on the ideas of the 18th century enlighteners, taking into account the achievements of modern scientific and technological progress and transformed to meet the “demands of the time”? Or is the movement towards a bright future, the pursuit of happiness as the main goal of humanity seen by thinkers of the past and today’s transhumanists in completely different ways? The authors turn to the scientific heritage of J.A. Condorcet, containing ideas of progress that served as a certain guideline in the course of subsequent social transformations. The representative of the French Enlightenment saw the potential for human improvement in the development of intelligence, morality, science, art, literature, believing that the main guarantee of achieving success in this field is ensuring the availability of universal education. Condorcet sets a high standard for the future, an example of the proper attitude of the state to the education and upbringing of its citizens, not leaving aside the importance of such material driving forces of progress as the development of industry, agriculture, etc. The work emphasizes that, despite all the utopian views of the enlighteners, their ideas about the power of reason have not lost their significance today, since they represent strategic guidelines for the elevation of each person, his spiritual growth due to a decent education and upbringing, familiarization with new knowledge, the disclosure of creative abilities, i.e. through personal and cultural improvement.



The Views of Ancient Philosophers and Modern Criminal Law
Abstract
The research emphasizes the demand for the philosophy of criminal law as such, as well as reveals the ways of application of philosophical knowledge by criminal law specialists. As it is known, philosophical teaching helps to understand the essence of specific phenomena or events with the help of appropriate tools, forming a complete picture of existence and its components. Such a doctrine is necessary today for those who produce exclusively scientific and legal knowledge in any objective form and those engaged in lawmaking and law-enforcement activities. Science has always demanded philosophical thought of criminal law, and their close relationship is traced in the most significant works of prominent philosophers since ancient times. The authors emphasize the unique value of philosophical teachings of the ancient period for modern criminal law, which, even nowadays, is based mainly on the postulates of the philosophers of Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome. The conceptual foundations of these philosophical views have demonstrated their significance over the millennia, and this study highlights the need for their scientific rethinking and the use of the latter’s results in legislative and law enforcement activities. Rethinking the philosophical works of the Antique period by modern lawyers will allow us to clearly build a hierarchy of values protected in the modern world, confirm the principles of the rule of law, and rationally assess the role of criminal punishment and other criminal legal institutions.



G.W. Leibniz’s Metaphysics in the Philosophy of Gilles Deleuze: From Ontology to Ethics
Abstract
This study is a detailed analysis of the influence of the philosophy of G.W. Leibniz on the metaphysics and ethics of Gilles Deleuze, with a focus on the transformation of Leibniz’s key concepts within Deleuze’s philosophical system. Particular attention is paid to the evolution of Deleuze’s perception of Leibniz’s philosophy: from the critical perception presented in early works such as “Difference and Repetition” and “Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza”, where Leibniz is interpreted as a philosopher of transcendental representation, to the integration of Leibniz’s key concepts into Deleuze’s own philosophical system, which is particularly evident in “The Fold. Leibniz and the Baroque”. The study focuses on Deleuze’s revision of the principles of identity and non-contradiction - which he reinterprets in the context of his ontology of events, series and singularities. The focus is on how Deleuze replaces Leibniz’s theological perspective with an immanent system in which the harmony of the world is based on a mathematically optimal distribution of singularities. Deleuze’s ethical project is examined through the lens of the concept of puissance (force, power, potency), which combines the ideas of Nietzsche, Spinoza and Leibniz. The study emphasises the significance of interrelated categories such as the will to power, the capacity for action and potency, which become the basis of Deleuze’s ethical system. Chaos and difference are seen not as destructive forces, but as grounds for the formation of a dynamic harmony that unites disparate elements into a coherent system. The study is characterized by a unique approach that combines Deleuze’s metaphysics and ethics, as well as an original interpretation of his interaction with Leibniz’s philosophy. The author argues that Deleuze forms a unique view of the world as a process where chaos and difference act as the foundations for dynamic harmony. This approach allows Deleuze to combine elements of Leibniz’s and Nietzsche’s theories, presenting our world as the best possible world because of its ability to maintain maximum variety while preserving wholeness.



ONTOLOGY AND GNOSEOLOGY
Twenty-Seven Answers to One Question
Abstract
In his Novum Organum, F. Bacon put forward the idea of “prerogative instances” as a means of shortening the paths of putting forward and testing hypotheses. Bacon’s “prerogative instances” are considered in the research as a possible answer to J.S. Mill’s question about why in some cases one example is enough for complete induction, while in other cases even myriads of mutually agreeing examples are not enough for a reliable conclusion. It is shown how the assessment of “prerogative instances” and F. Bacon’s theory of induction itself changed among historians of philosophy and science throughout the 19th-20th centuries. The classification of “prerogative instances” carried out by F. Bacon is analyzed, and its weak points are identified. The author’s classification of “prerogative instances” based on F. Bacon’s ideas is proposed, and the possibility and prospects of alternative approaches to such classification are assessed. The place of “prerogative instances” in F. Bacon’s general theory of induction is considered. It is shown that some of them can be used before compiling the “tables of presence”, “tables of absence” and “tables of degrees” that form the basis of F. Bacon’s method of eliminative induction, another part should be placed in these tables, and the third part can be applied after the corresponding hypotheses have been put forward on the basis of the tables. A distinction is made between induction as a derivation of universal hypotheses from singular premises and induction as a method of empirical research that allows one to put forward and test generalizing hypotheses on the basis of individual facts. It is noted that the fair criticism of induction as an unreliable conclusion was unjustifiably transferred to induction as a method in the post-positivist philosophy of science of the 20th century. The possibility of using “prerogative instances” as heuristic methods of putting forward and testing hypotheses, the effectiveness of which depends on the adopted metaphysical assumptions, is indicated in those modern theories of induction that reject the idea of constructing a universal inductive method.



Explication of the Concept of Reality in the Digital Age: Issues of Theory and Methodology
Abstract
Due to the explosive development of info-communication technologies and the equally explosive transformation of human and social life that followed, philosophers and publicists have started talking about digital reality. Apparently, the time has come to deal with that reality or even with the set of realities that have emerged during the pre-digital era. First, this is necessary for a better understanding of the nature and essence of digital reality itself, and, second, it is important for the most accurate assessment of the prospects of its interaction with pre-digital realities. Thus, in the 20th century, two main ways of constructing pre-digital reality were identified and described, or, more precisely, two models of reality identification were proposed. The first model was constructed using the means of neo-Kantian and phenomenological philosophy of science (Cogen, Cassirer, Husserl), while the second model was born at the junction of pragmatist psychology, phenomenological sociology and sociology of knowledge (Jаmes, Schutz, Berger, Lukman). What unites these models is that reality (unlike things) is not given to us in our direct experience and is not constituted in the direct sense of the word (unlike the world or being). The author proceeds from the assumption that in studying the formation of digital reality it is necessary to use the experience of predecessors and test the hypothesis that digital reality has the properties of both physical and everyday (social) reality. Just like the construction of physical reality and the social construction of everyday reality, the construction of digital reality should prove to be a spontaneous process in all its dimensions. It is also important to understand whether the construction of digital reality is a separate process running in parallel with the construction of theoretical realities and everyday realities, or whether it is the digitalisation of already existing realities.



SCHOLARLY LIFE
Kant’s Interpretation of the Reflective Faculty of Judgment as a “Proto-Hermeneutics”: Review of the Book “The Roots of Hermeneutics in Kant’s Reflective-Teleological Judgment” by H. Ruthrof
Abstract
The review is focused on the analysis of H. Ruthrof’s book based on the belief that I. Kant’s “Critique of Judgment” contains a detailed platform of “proto-hermeneutics”. This work is considered as the basis for the subsequent formation and development of a variety of hermeneutical schools. Examining the content of this academically significant and valuable history of philosophy study, based on a large number of carefully analyzed sources and interdisciplinary material, the review authors polemically discuss Ruthrof’s approach to the second part of the third critique as the main fragment of Kant’s work containing the roots of hermeneutic thinking developed in the doctrine of reflective-teleological judgment. The authors substantiate the thesis that the foundations of hermeneutical thinking are laid by the categorical structure of the third critique in its entirety, the whole set of ideas developed in its context about the dynamics of the relationship between experience, productive imagination, intellect, both the determining and the reflective ability of judgment, which depend on the meaning-creation activity of reason. This allows them to consider the subject of cultural creativity in the unity of the cognitive, aesthetic and moral vectors of his activity. It is shown that the birth and subsequent development of hermeneutics is associated with a essential rethinking of the provisions of the third critique in terms of emphasizing the historical and linguistic aspects of human creativity. The classification of schools of hermeneutics proposed by the book’s author is considered in detail, which allows to evaluate his significant contribution to understanding the specifics of the evolution of this trend of post-classical philosophical thought.





